Wednesday, May 1, 2024

The Trustful Approach: an Introduction

The trustful approach is a philosophical exercise that teaches you peace of mind and confidence in the face of political disagreement and social discord.

How can we live with the shocking behaviour of some of our fellow citizens? Everyday, people show commitment to beliefs and deeds that we think are wrong. When they are morally wrong, we feel utterly bewildered by their conduct: how can we make sense of it? “What are they even thinking? How dare they?” From our point of view, the minds of the people who engage in those wrongdoings feel strange, incomprehensible, and hostile. While thinking about how far they have fallen, we feel powerless. It seems impossible to get through to them. And over time, all of this wears us down.

We need tools to address how stressful this experience is. Like many negative experiences, it can come to dominate our lives, if we’re not careful. This can make us the worst versions of ourselves, leading us to betray our own values, including the values we accuse others of disrespecting.

I would like to propose a philosophical exercise designed specifically to deal with this feeling of moral shock. My idea is that if you practice this exercise regularly, you will be more resilient in the face of those challenges. They will feel less bad, and be less disorienting. You will be able to meet those instances of bewilderment, without losing all of your peace of mind, energy, and focus. At the same time, I recognize that those unpleasant experiences are important to our sense of morality, and so I have taken care to design the exercise in such a way that it doesn’t entail compromising on our values or letting go of legitimate indignation.

The exercise in question is called the “trustful approach”. In a sense, it is about trusting yourself and trusting your opponent more. But the devil is in the details. It is not about compromising on one’s values. The exercise is essentially about becoming aware of the rumination we engage in when we try to understand what someone was thinking when they did or said something wrong. There are certain things that are important to notice about this state of mind. Noticing them brings a lot of clarity to the situation and frees your mind from unnecessary suffering.

So here’s how you practice the trustful approach: the most important thing is to notice when you are in a state of moral shock, and to try to contemplate that emotion with as much curiosity as possible. Contemplating this feeling leads you to observe this desire that you have of knowing what goes on in the mind of the offender who said or did something wrong. This moral shock feels like a frustration of that desire. Crucially, you can pay attention to the various interpretations that come to mind as to what the offender was likely thinking. How you interpret what they meant to do or say. You are paying attention to the process of trying to fulfil that desire, of trying to find closure through hypotheses. In particular, you can be mindful of the way you form such hypotheses, how you linger on them for moral support, and how you discard them, as you eventually become dissatisfied with them. Over time, you will learn to realize how strangely inept those interpretations can be, since often their only virtue is to promise that they will finally put your mind at ease – by uncovering the secret motive of the offender – and they routinely fail to live up to that promise. But in order to realize this, you need to become adept at noticing two key aspects of the experience of moral shock.

Indeed, upon paying attention, you need to perform a double clarification of your experience. Paying attention to these feelings leads you to uncover two ambiguities that you can dispel.

The first clarification answers the question “Am I shocked or am I surprised?”. Though shock should be understood as a form of surprise, it is not necessarily reducible to the kind of surprise we experience when something goes against our expectations. Firstly, the shocking behaviour might have been fully expected, and we still feel strongly about it. Secondly, if all we cared about was predicting the future, we would respond to the offence by simply revising our expectations as to how the offender is likely to behave in the future, and then move on. However, what matters when we are shocked is not that a predictive expectation failed, but that a moral expectation was breached. Moral standards dictate how one should behave, not how one is likely to behave, so it is no wonder that we do not easily move on. No matter how much information we gather or guess about the offender, moral shock can always renew our curiosity: we can always ask “But how could this be?!” and truly mean it as a question. This allows rumination. Moral standards are there to convince people to do better, and are able to create new expectations. “I still expect you to do better.” Thus, the desire to know what they are thinking is marked by a fundamental ambiguity: are you trying to read their mind or are you trying to shape their mind? Are you truly wondering what they think or are you arguing with them inside your head, expecting them to change? It is good to become aware of the fact that your curiosity towards the mind of the offender is underpinned by a desire to repair the norm that was disrespected, bringing with it the hope of getting them to admit what they did wrong and the despair of thinking you might not be able to. Neither this hope nor this despair are appropriate during rumination, as rumination is not a proper way to reach people and change them.

The second clarification answers the question “Who believes what?” Because rumination based on moral shock thrives on the ambiguity between trying to read the mind of others and trying to shape the mind of others, it becomes difficult to remember to whom the values and beliefs that you ponder actually belong. The process of realizing that you are fundamentally trying to regain confidence about the validity of the norm that the offender disrespected should culminate in the realization that these values and beliefs you are considering are yours, and not that of the offender. Instead of realizing that, we tend to come up with “incredulous interpretations” of the deeds and words of the people who offend us. Interpretations marked by utter disbelief that they could be motivated by different values or beliefs. For instance, we might hastily hypothesize “They knew it was wrong but they did it to hurt me” or “They knew it was wrong but they did it to attract attention”, which is incoherent since this premise “they knew it was wrong” consists essentially in attributing to them the values and beliefs that we have, and that they manifestly lacked in the moment of doing something wrong. In other words, we refuse to let go of the idea that the cause of their behaviour can be understood using our beliefs; we refuse to believe they could think differently. This influences how we interpret the justifications offered by the offender. We interpret them in an incredulous way, refusing to consider that they might be a sincere expression of what motivated the offender, while at the same time hoping they can serve as an accidental confession that we are right. The fact of the matter is that people are usually more than happy to communicate their true motives, as far as they understand them, since they are very proud of those motives. Those motives are based on their values and beliefs, how could they not be proud of it? On the contrary, the incredulous approach allows us to ruminate on our own, because it allows us to fantasize that in committing the offence, the offender paradoxically recognized the importance of the norm that they disrespected, which makes it so taking seriously their point of view and how it differs from ours completely superfluous. In this situation, rumination feels like a great use of one’s time. But it is unhelpful, as it promises us that we can relate to the offender, while creating the conditions that make it impossible to relate to them, thus increasing the feeling of despair, the suspicion that the offender can’t be reached and reasoned with.

In summary: The trustful approach is practiced by mindfully paying attention to the feeling of moral shock. This feeling features a frustrated desire to know what is happening in the mind of the offender. This desire has to be examined and clarified in two ways. Firstly, “Am I shocked or am I surprised?” Shock is not always the kind of surprise that has to do with a failure of predictive expectations. It is about moral standards. Therefore, shocked curiosity can only be satisfied by knowing what to do with the situation. Can I change this person or is now not the right moment? Secondly, “Who believes what?”, when knowing the mind of the offender is caught up in trying to change the mind of the offender, it becomes difficult to keep straight who believes what. We easily forget that the offender has different beliefs. This creates a lot of needless confusion. In the end, I learn to trust my values and beliefs more, and to not be insecure about them in a way that leads me to produce incredulous interpretations of the justifications people give of their actions.

This entire exercise brings peace of mind by stopping the cognitive machinery that gets activated in order to call out the offender and change their behaviour, even when there is no plausible path to achieve such a thing. Thus we can save our energy until we find the appropriate forum to mobilize those efforts. Since the exercise prevents us from generating inept hypotheses and distrustful theories that we cling to for relief, it means that once we have found this forum, we are in a better position to change the minds of other people, and/or to have our own mind changed in the attempt, because we are primarily attentive to the way they are thinking, and not to the way we wish they would think.


P.S: Though I do practice this exercise myself, and it does me a lot of good, all of this is still very experimental, and I am always trying to refine the design and the pedagogy of the exercise. This is why I need people to test it out. If you would like to talk about your experience practicing this exercise, or reading this text, or if you are willing to give it a try but are still unsure how to go about it and would like some guidance, please contact me at this email address: lemiroirtranquille@outlook.fr . I am very open to any feedback or any dialogue about this.


Pierrick Simon

01/05/2024

my email: lemiroirtranquille@outlook.fr

(do not hesitate to reach out)

Bluesky: @pierricksimon.bsky.social

Twitter: @PhiloTranquille

Tuesday, April 2, 2024

Spinozist Mindfulness & Loving Kindness

(The plan? To try one new philosophical exercise every month. This article is part of a series. In the previous episode, we explored Postural Yoga and the sense of earth)

For the month of March, I tried to practice Spinozist mindfulness. It’s not that “Spinozist mindfulness” is an established practice, mind you. I just wanted to see if it could be! In the end, my impression is that Spinoza and mindfulness are not a perfect match. However, they are far from being a bad match. I don’t know if my impression is correct, and I suspect that verifying it would require no less than answering some very thorny questions of Spinoza scholarship (more on that later). My tentative speculation is that the paradigmatic Spinozist practice of recalling the philosophical system laid out in the Ethics might be closer to loving kindness meditation, not mindfulness.

All of this pondering started as I was reading Christos Hadjioannou’s excellent article about what a Stoic version or a Heideggerian version of mindfulness would be or could be1. I became fascinated by the question of what criteria we should use to claim that a certain philosophy could have or did have a version of mindfulness. A sort of phenomenological training regimen for your attention, inclined towards the ideas and values of a particular philosophy. I was very excited about this, because depending on what the answer is to this question, it could potentially mean that there are many flavours of mindfulness one could try out. Including mindfulness variants for some western philosophies that lack a focused exercise.

I decided to try to combine Spinozist philosophy and mindfulness, since it was on my mind for a reason I will touch on at the end of this post. I studied the Ethics again, and I practiced mindfulness meditation (I do it all the time already). As much as I could, I tried to combine the two. I tried to have mindfulness meditation be the catalyst that would elicit the assimilation of the lessons from the Ethics. And I tried to have the lessons from the Ethics support my mindfulness practice.

It is crystal clear that Spinozist philosophy is a way of life2. You are meant to assimilate this philosophy so that it changes your personality and the way you see the world. The goal is happiness, or liberation, however you want to call it. This fact of the matter is a good starting point because in order for a philosophy to be eligible for a mindfulness variant, it must be a way of life. Philosophy as a Way of Life triggers the necessary shift in perspective. It is hard to characterize this newly found point of view, but perhaps one way to describe it is that it is a type of meta-cognition (thinking about thinking) that adds a particular pragmatic dimension to your cognition: the issue of good timing. The quality of one’s thoughts will be judged by whether or not they are likely to swoop down just in time to rescue you from akrasia. In anticipation of this moment, the good quality of the thought is achieved by paying attention to timing (How many times did you push yourself to remember the salvific idea? How much did you linger on it? Did you identify the crucial times when you should push yourself to remember it?) This point of view allows you to appreciate differently things that the layperson (or philosophers not versed in philosophy as a way of life) might consider to be non-rational nudges derailing your thinking (imagination, repetition, idea association, somatics, theatrics, etc ; anything that gives you “cultish brain-washing” vibes basically). On the contrary, to the Way of Life philosopher, it seems that those elements can be indirectly rational, as they further one’s thinking against akrasia, improving one’s cognition by deepening it, as long as it is in the service of good cognitive timing. This shift in perspective is a necessary condition for mindfulness, because mindfulness opacity3, the ability to see thoughts as thoughts in such a way that it leaves a lasting and beneficial impression, relies on this way of life perspective.

Yet, this necessary condition of being a way of life, is not a sufficient condition. And this is the reason why I am not convinced Spinozist philosophy is a perfect match for mindfulness. To be sure, if you look at the remedies to the passions that Spinoza proposes4, you see a lot of things that are very mindfulness-friendly. Not only is it compatible with mindfulness, but it is actively encouraging you to pay attention to things that are very good targets for mindfulness practice.

One remedy is knowledge of the affects: when passions hurt us, it means that they are passive affects. They are passive because we have a confused idea of them. However, it is possible to become aware of them, to form a distinct and clear idea of them, and to therefore convert them into active affects, which no longer hurt. This is very reminiscent of mindfulness, where active awareness of a passion removes its sting.

Another remedy is removing the idea of an external cause: I am not sure that my interpretation of this one is correct, but the way I have been practicing this was always to dispel confusion about free will. Spinoza tells us that we mistakenly think that we have free will because we are not thinking clearly about the causes that determine our actions. I often use that reasoning on myself, but I also use that reasoning on people who have offended me. I remove the idea of an external cause by ceasing to arbitrarily delineate the offender as the sole cause of my hurt. The whole of Nature has conspired to cause the event, so why arbitrarily think about what I confusedly take to be the free will of the offender? And then, as Spinoza points out, I cannot be mad at the whole of Nature, given that to know its necessity is to love it. As far as I am concerned, removing the idea of an external cause was always about deflating the motivation for arbitrarily singling out the last domino in the chain of cause and effect. I don’t know if this is the right interpretation of this second remedy, but I have been practising that for years now, and it has done me a lot of good!

Those two remedies call for a certain way of paying attention to your experience. A way that is pretty close to mindfulness meditation. But is it the same way of paying attention? When it comes to the debate of whether mindfulness should be characterized as relying on wiser judgments or as relying on a non-judgemental attitude, I always try to hold both together. I feel like it has to be two ways of describing the same thing. The hermeneutical characterization of the efficacy of mindfulness (which describes the practice as equipping you with better notions to interpret phenomena) and the bare attention characterization of the efficacy of mindfulness (which describes it as shedding unhelpful notions and paying attention to phenomena themselves) must work together. But for our purpose, the bare attention characterization comes to the foreground, because the hermeneutical characterization alone could mislead us into thinking that being a way of life is sufficient to offer a version of mindfulness: after all, if this philosophy has something interesting to say about the wise life, it means that it equips us with better notions to interpret phenomena... and if that’s all there is to mindfulness, then it is sufficient to have a mindfulness variant. The question then becomes: is there a bare attention exercise that we can extract from Spinoza’s philosophy?

This question was brought to my attention by the difficulty I had to make compatible my study of Spinoza’s system and the largely non-verbal nature of my mindfulness practice. Bare attention is a training in non-verbal phenomenality: it is about attending to phenomena as they are, inherently meaningful even before we apply our linguistic schemes onto them. This requires a concept of suspension, of refraining from judgment. This concept is something that the Stoics and the phenomenologists like Heidegger have, which makes them good candidates for mindfulness. Is this something that Spinoza has as well? In Spinozist scholarship, there is a debate as to the link between what he calls the second kind of knowledge (reason) and the third kind of knowledge (intuition): is there a gradual continuity between the two, or is there a qualitative jump, a leap in kind, between the two? This question matters because reason employs language, whereas intuition holds blessedness, the highest good of Spinoza’s philosophy. Do we suspend other kinds of knowledge in order to access the intuitive kind? When I had first encountered Spinoza, I had assumed that there was a kind of jump between the two, but how much of that was informed by my non-verbal meditation practice? And to be frank, how much of that was motivated by wanting to agree with Spinoza’s conclusion without actually attending to the weird idiosyncratic steps he thinks are important to get there (the geometry!)? The bridge between those two kinds of knowledge might be the “geometric order” of his demonstrations, that Spinoza lays out in the Ethics, but am I really invested in that, or is it just, to me, a quirky layout on the page? I have always taken this order to be important mnemonically: it helps you remember the system. Is that enough to be invested? I don’t know. Maybe. For Philosophy as a Way of Life, mnemonics is not a superficial affair, an after-thought: the entire point is to remember wisdom!

I do not have the answers to these difficult Spinoza scholarship questions. I do not hope to answer these questions this month, unfortunately. I can only try out things and see how they feel. This month, it felt to me that Spinozist meditation had to be a constructive style of meditation. It has been proposed that there are three types of meditation5: attentional exercises, deconstructive exercises, constructive exercises.

- Mindfulness is an attentional exercise. As Jan Puc argues6, with mindfulness, you train yourself to pay attention to the appearance and disappearance of phenomena, refraining from elaborating or developing the object of attention, and therefore stopping the spread of its affective force in consciousness.

- Deconstructive exercises deflate certain experiential schemes by pointing directly to them and revealing them as constructed (not basic) and, in fact, baseless (insight into the absence of enduring self, insight into non-duality).

- Constructive exercises, such as loving kindness, work by voluntarily fostering a specific feeling or mood in your experience. It is marked by a clear preference towards a state of mind that you cultivate.

I think that the standard mindfulness curriculum7 tries to touch on some deconstructive and constructive aspects, but they can be a bit optional. Similarly, I feel that Spinoza’s philosophy has many resources that touch on all of these things: attention, deconstruction, construction. All of it is in there, in some way. However the way the entire philosophical system hang together inspired me to practice it like one would “loving kindness”: fostering blessedness voluntarily, while relying on common notions and imagination, but in an enlightened way.

Though common notions and imagination do not belong to the third kind of knowledge (the best one), they seem to allow for some good things to happen. One remedy that Spinoza proposes against the passions is the “re-ordering of the affects”. I didn’t know what it meant, so it had to be explained to me by secondary literature, and here is the explanation that I was given:

It is an activity that we can intentionally perform to diminish the force of our passions. It is based upon the power that he believes the human mind has to intentionally join two ideas to one another by frequently thinking about them in unison, so that when the first idea occurs, the second idea is naturally aroused in the mind as well. One of the ways in which we may apply this power is by intentionally joining passionate affects together with mottos or rules, “sure maxims of life,” that are rational to follow whenever those passions take hold of us (E5p10s, G II/287).”8

If this is correct, and if you see, as I do, the last two remedies - “the endurance of rational affects” and the “multiplicity of the causes of rational affects” – as creating this sort of highway that lets you gain a lot of momentum while you become more and more active in fostering feelings of love, then it would stand to reason that enacting Spinoza’s system would be very similar to a loving kindness practice. I might be biased, because the reason why Spinoza was on my mind when I started all of this is that I wanted a remedy to my constant anxious rumination. I came to see rumination as this network of bad feelings9, self-reinforcing, each unhappy passion leading back to all the others like some kind of sad maze. It seemed like Spinoza was proposing the opposite: building a network of self-reinforcing good feelings. And I must say that it works on me! One of my biggest flaws as a meditator is that I tend to focus exclusively on attentional and deconstructive exercises. Thus, I keep shooting down inadequate ideas without ever thinking to put something better in their place. It’s like playing whack-a-mole, playing defense, and never building something better. Spinoza’s philosophy is such a good fit for that unfortunate gap in my spiritual life.


Pierrick Simon

02/04/2024

my email: lemiroirtranquille@outlook.fr

(do not hesitate to reach out)

Bluesky: @pierricksimon.bsky.social

Twitter: @PhiloTranquille

1“Heideggerian and Stoic Mindfulness” by Christos Hadjioannou in The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Mindfulness

2 https://pwl.fcsh.unl.pt/project/ to know more about Philosophy as a Way of Life

3Victor Lange, Thor Grünbaum, Transparency and the Mindfulness Opacity Hypothesis, The Philosophical Quarterly, 2023;, pqad098, https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqad098

4In the scholia of Proposition XX, of part 5 of the Ethics (“Of the Power of the Intellect, or of Human Freedom”)

5 Cortland J. Dahl, Antoine Lutz, Richard J. Davidson ; Reconstructing and deconstructing the self: cognitive mechanisms in meditation practice ; Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Volume 19, Issue 9, 2015, ; https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.001.

6Puc, J. (2019). In Defence of Bare Attention: A Phenomenological Interpretation of Mindfulness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 (5-6):170-190.

7https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mindfulness-based_stress_reduction

8https://iep.utm.edu/spin-mor/#H3 “Benedict De Spinoza: Moral Philosophy” by John Grey in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

9 Thanks to this article : Russell, Jodie Louise (2021). Stuck on repeat: Why do we continue to ruminate? Synthese 199 (5-6):13143-13162.

Thursday, February 29, 2024

Postural Yoga and the sense of earth

 (The plan? To try one new philosophical exercise each month. This article is thus part of a series. January was all about Anti-Curiosity Exercises)

    I saw an amazing academic talk, which renewed my enthusiasm for Yoga, and which prompted me to try out a different way of going about my Yoga practice (which I had mostly abandoned, like I do regularly). The talk in question was given by Hayden Kee and was called “Embodiment, Disembodiment, Reembodiment: Insights from Phenomenology and Postural Yoga”1 (available on Youtube, see footnote). I also read the corresponding article2, which I thought was worth it to go slightly more in depth with some ideas. Now, to be fair, I was already enthusiastic about Yoga. Mostly because it does me a lot of good whenever I go back to it. Yoga allows me to break through the false sense that I am a little homunculus living inside my skull and piloting a machine of limbs, as a puppeteer would a puppet. As a practice, it cures me of a kind of subject/object dualism that sees my body as merely an object hosting my subjectivity. However, if this talk renewed my enthusiasm, it’s because it suggested that Yoga could bring you even more insights than that, all the while focusing only on modern postural yoga3, which I thought was very relatable and exciting.

    Hayden Kee highlights three phenomenological insights in particular: “(1) the grounding and openness of the body; (2) the reflexivity of the body; and (3) the illuminating awareness of the proprioceptive, minimal, body-schematic self.”4

1) The first one has to do with becoming aware of yourself as a “gravitational being”, pulled towards the earth by gravity (what I would like to call the “sense of earth”), but also as a being which is exposed to the world (what I would call the “sense of sky”). For the latter point about exposure, Hayden Kee draws on Merleau Ponty’s concept of dehiscence of the flesh (“the term alludes to the radical openness of our sensing bodies to the surrounding world5) and to the fact that many Yoga postures seem to express a desire for exposing our bodies, even our insides, to the world, in a very vulnerable way.

2) The second point has to do with experiencing our bodies as both touching and touched, subject and object, which is crucial for developing a sense of intersubjectivity (others too are as much subject as they are object).

3) The third point has to do with cultivating an explicit awareness of the body which is nonetheless different from one’s body image (one’s conceptual understanding of, emotional attitude towards, and indirect feel for the body6). This is a controversial claim that runs counter the phenomenologists who think that explicit awareness of the body always has to do with body image, not body schema.

    You do not have to practice postural yoga, or any kind of yoga, in order to have those insights. However, I really like Hayden Kee’s suggestion that extraordinary experiences sometimes help. As he explains, touching your right hand with your left hand (and thus experiencing the reversibility of the flesh, the touching/touched nature of your body) is an experience so common that it might fail to elicit surprise and wonder. Whereas in some of those more extraordinary postures, you might be positively astonished to find that you come to grab your foot behind your ear. What is it doing there? Is it an object or a subject? Is it mine? Yes, philosophical wonder can be ignited by the most mundane of things, but it is also typically elicited by the most grandiose of things. The amazing quote (of doubtful origin7) “In the absence of any other proof, the thumb alone would convince me of God's existence” is an example of how someone could marvel at something as common as a thumb. But throughout history, people tend to marvel at bigger things such as the starry night sky and the entire cosmos it shows8. I suppose, what I was in the mood to try out, was having a go at extraordinary wonder for a change. As a philosopher, I always try to cultivate wonder for the seemingly ordinary. I wanted to try something different. I wanted to experience my body as a place of extraordinary marvels and wonders. (while being very careful not to break anything, of course)

    One of the most wonderful things I found in this talk and article, is the way Hayden Kee talks about Tree Pose.


(an image, by Phoenix Li, depicting Tree pose, and found in Hayden Kee's article)


The description is so good that I simply have to quote it extensively, while highlighting in bold the passages I find most beautiful:

“Consider a simple posture such as tree pose (virkasana – see figure 1). The practitioner balances on one foot. The other leg is bent at the knee and opened to the side. The sole of the foot of the bent leg is placed firmly into the inner thigh of the standing leg. There are many variations for the hands and arms. The hands may be placed in prayer position in front of the heart, or the arms may reach up to the sky like branches of a tree. The gaze may be fixed straight ahead or at a point on the floor, or the eyes may converge on the tip of the nose, look up, or even close.

Even a simple asana such as this requires considerable awareness and education to be executed expertly. Though there is hardly a major muscle group of the body that is not involved in this posture, brute strength and flexibility alone are not sufficient. The body schema must be coordinated and cultivated. In the absence of this training, the novice wavers like a sapling in the wind. In response, he focuses attention on different regions of the proprioceptive body to stabilize the posture. Aspects of the sensorimotor body schema he had previously not attended to suddenly become salient. A precise activation of the standing foot is required to maintain a broad and steady foundation for the pose. However, as the novice directs attention to the standing foot to train its activation, he may find that the buttocks has gone soft. Weight shifts away from the midline resulting in an overall imbalanced posture. The tree wobbles. The correct degree of reciprocal isometric force between the bent leg through the sole of the foot and the inner thigh of the standing leg will help restore equilibrium towards the midline. But in focusing on this aspect of the pose, the practitioner may lose the correct activation of the standing foot, or the deep core muscles may become unstable, and now integrity is lost elsewhere in the body. To hold all of this together at once

demands experimenting and cultivating a new awareness – a kind of new body babbling through which we (re)educate the body schema. Eventually, once these local microattunements have become incorporated into an overall structure of bodily comportment, awareness may become less localized. For the expert, awareness may be more a general, monitoring field encompassing the whole balancing body rooted to the earth, balancing in space. She makes minute adjustments in any area where a slight loss of integrity might arise, but without losing awareness of the global integrity of the posture. She stands like a redwood, slow and stable in the winds, adjusting almost imperceptibly.”9

    After reading all of this, and being so moved by the tree metaphor, I decided that a significant part of my practice this month would be dedicated to mastering such poses, and to experiencing the sense of earth and sky, as well as the other phenomenological insights. While I initially planned to train for several such poses, I became instead uniquely captivated and intrigued by this one, Tree Pose. Its challenge was perfect for me. Everytime I started worrying about whether or not I would find interesting things to say for my blog article at the end of the month, the tree wobbled, as a penalty for my distraction. Everytime I became mindful of how much I rely on thinking about my body in a literally visual way (my body image), the balancing act was there to make even more obvious the price I paid for such a reliance.

    Indeed, because I wanted to stop relying on sight so much in my thinking, I decided to close my eyes while I was doing Tree Pose. To my great surprise, I started wobbling and falling pretty much as soon as I closed them. I couldn’t believe how quick it was! But then I remembered why that might be the case. Though the sense of sight might not look like it is contributing all that much to the act of balancing, it is actually contributing quite a lot. And so if you’re not relying on your eyes, you’re entirely relying on your inner ear or on something like that, to achieve balance. It’s very difficult! So difficult that I took it as a challenge.

    I found it near impossible to regain balance with my eyes closed once I started wobbling in Tree Pose. The trick, then, was to not start wobbling in the first place. As much as possible, to remain steady while entering the pose, and to stay that way. Right entry into the pose was crucial. Interestingly, what that looked like concretely was a sort of stronger relationship to the earth. I had to anchor myself down. Bending the knees more, gripping with my feet, as if I were taking roots. I also found it helpful to use the kind of breath that is located in the throat, and which sounds like the waves of the ocean. That kind of breathing brought a sort of steadiness and resoluteness to my whole body.

    The exercise was quite stimulating. After doing it for a bit, I was surprised to find that I spontaneously developed some habits that are strikingly similar to my mindfulness practice. First of all, I started to enjoy falling and coming back to the center. What I had experienced as failure and frustration at first (wobbling and falling) now was the surest sign that I was trying, a completely legitimate part of the exercise, as enjoyable as the other half of it, which consisted in not falling. Secondly, something that developed almost without any conscious decision on my part, is that I started falling into a rhythm of performing Tree Pose with my eyes open, and then gradually closing them down, as if to gradually increase the difficulty. This was very cool, as it was strikingly reminiscent of how I’ll regularly test myself during meditation. When I meditate, I try to achieve a state of non-duality where the distinction between subject and world falls away, and whenever I achieve that state somewhat, I gently test it out, putting pressure on it to test the strength of it. It feels like throwing a little wrench into the exercise to see how I cope: I think about something which is usually unpleasant, or I think about the uncertain future, or I ask myself “Who are you?” to see what answer first comes to mind. All those things test out my equanimity. Here in Tree Pose, I felt drawn to giving myself a little challenging push from time to time by closing my eyes and seeing how I fare.

    In the end, here’s the result of that little experiment:

- I did manage to experience surprise and wonder in circumstances that are not ordinary for me. Circumstances requiring discipline, micro-adjustments in service of a goal, not in service of comfort. A Yoga practice that is more ambitious than I am used to.

- I did manage to challenge my reliance on visual thinking. The “body image” does not have to be literally visual for other people, but it is for me, and it is something I wrestle with in my spiritual life. Any challenge to it constitutes a welcome change. A relief, in fact!

- I did manage to get in touch with a certain sense of the earth. Feeling gravity, feeling support against my body, even the pleasure of falling. The clichéd poetry of it was revitalized and replaced by a poetry that moved me, through the metaphor of the swaying tree, through the idea that one can intensify and refine one’s body schema without overthinking it. I don’t know what connection this sense of earth could have to other phenomenological theories.. let’s say, Husserl or Heidegger’s sense of earth for instance, but at least now I am curious about possible parallels or divergences.

- However, I did not manage to get the sense of the sky. Of what Hayden Kee calls the sense of “dehiscence”, of opening yourself up to the world around. I tried the most “aggressively” open poses while my visual thinking was still overwhelming. Therefore the “sense of sky” was completely covered up by vague concepts, clichéd poetry, and a relentless dualism. As for Tree Pose, I did not master it enough to feel any openness in my upper body. If anything, because of the challenge I had chosen for myself, my shoulders were hunched, and I was facing the ground exclusively ; holding on for dear life as the wind blows violently against the tree. A month was not enough to feel secure enough in the sense of earth to develop its correlate ; the sense of sky.

    All in all, since Hayden Kee has such cool things to say about dehiscence (in truth, it was originally what I found most inspiring about his talk) I vow to come back to postural Yoga another month and to write another article, this time about the sense of sky.


2Kee, Hayden. 2023. “Phenomenological Insights from Postural Yoga Practice.” In The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Mindfulness, edited by Susi Ferrarello and Christos Hadjioannou, 138–51. Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003350668-12.

3“Most of the dialogue between phenomenology and yoga thus far has occurred between the classical yoga of Patanjali and transcendental phenomenology, or between the Buddhist Yogacara tradition and phenomenology. Little attention has been paid to the more bodily focused practices of hatha yoga and its descendent, modern postural yoga.” Abstract of the article ; https://www.researchgate.net/publication/376336599_Phenomenological_Insights_from_Postural_Yoga_Practice

4 p 141

5 p 143

6 p 146

8 see "Wonderstruck: How Wonder and Awe Shape the Way We Think" by Helen De Cruz https://press.princeton.edu/books/hardcover/9780691232126/wonderstruck  

9 p 140-141

Tuesday, January 30, 2024

Anti-Curiosity Exercises, Plutarch, and Quitting Obsessions


    I am setting myself a challenge: in 2024, I commit to practicing one new philosophical exercise each month. And then write about it! For January 2024, I took on Plutarch’s anti-curiosity exercises, described in his essay On Curiosity.1 The reason why I selected this practice to start off the year is because I was wondering if these exercises could help counteract Obsessive Compulsive Disorder. I have OCD myself and I am part of a team of philosophers who is leading an inquiry into this condition. We are trying our best to put the voices of the people who have OCD at the center of the discussion. The project is called Stuck on the Puzzle2: it involves a podcast being produced, a blog calling for guest-posts, and hopefully, eventually, the design of a philosophical exercise that could perhaps help when dealing with OCD.


    Reflecting on my own OCD, I came to agree with Juliette Vazard’s assessment that this disorder must have something to do with a dysfunction of the mechanism that normally leads someone to pick out things worth inquiring into3. She describes two linked affective mechanisms: one mechanism to assess if a proposition has stakes that are pragmatically costly, thus deciding if the proposition is worth inquiring into in the first place, and another mechanism to assess if the belief we have on the proposed topic was formed in a safe way, making it likely to be accurate (thus securing a good inquiry). Her hypothesis is that anxiety plays a role in this process, which is healthy, but that it can all go wrong in the case of hyper-anxiety. What we get in the end is intrusive uncertainty, as opposed to productive uncertainty. It becomes difficult to assuage the signal that something is worth looking into properly, even after you’ve looked into it properly enough. The experience is quite destabilizing. I would say that the result is not unlike a hyper-anxious kind of curiosity. It makes us perceive a proposition as being full of new and worrying possibilities that we feel we could investigate if only we took the proper steps. This potential connection to curiosity is what made me think of Plutarch’s prescriptions.


    I had not read Plutarch’s essay On Curiosity before, even though hearing about his proposed philosophical training in passing had made enough of an impact on me to prompt me to give it a try. His prescriptions are about training yourself to be less curious about things that do not matter all that much. Plutarch suggests, for instance, that we might want to postpone opening official letters we receive, or that we might want to deliberately turn away from sources of gossip while out and about. I do practice those two things. When I feel that my eagerness to know what an important message says does not align with my deeper values, I try to re-prioritize things in my life, starting from postponing the opening of the message. When I walk past a newspaper stand that displays tabloids with sensational headlines, I unfocus my eyes or look away, because I don’t think it’s good for me to have any sort of curiosity towards that sort of thing. The point is to be wary of curiosity’s potential connection to unhealthy obsessions, and to quit it, in this very counter-intuitive way, emboldened by the thought that it is counter-intuitive only because of this obsessive background, which is safe to ignore. Plutarch talks derisively of the “strangle-hold”4 that things can have on us. For instance, he recounts an anecdote which, in a way, pits an athlete against someone in the audience: “when Diogenes​ saw the Olympic victor Dioxippus making his triumphal entry in his chariot and unable to tear his eyes away from a beautiful woman who was among the spectators of the procession, but continually turning around and throwing side-glances in her direction, "Do you see," said the Cynic, "how a slip of a girl gets a strangle-hold on our athlete?" And you may observe how every kind of spectacle alike gets a strangle-hold on busybodies and twists their necks round when they once acquire a habit and practice of scattering their glances in all directions.” A lot of the examples he uses in his essay are steeped in sexism and classism, but if one manages to put that aside, one can be swayed by the main point, which is to regain some autonomy regarding the things that capture our attention.


    As for the main point of the essay, some adjustments are needed as well depending on what you want to do with it. He treats curiosity as a “disease”. As is often the case with ancient philosophers, this makes the relevance of his wisdom ambiguous for the purpose of treating actual mental disorders. What seems at first to invite a point of connection between his theory and psychopathology is undermined by the description of quite ordinary passions as pathological. When ordinary passions are described as illnesses, this sometimes precludes rather than allows a distinction between healthy states of mind and unhealthy ones. When the point is mainly to cure the folly of humanity, the difference between patients and non-patients gets lost. While Plutarch does not think everyone is under the sway of this unhealthy curiosity, the point remains that what he says is a “malady of the mind” is not actually an illness, but has a more universal character. What Plutarch describes is a moral vice, and though he might want to convince the reader that it is both a moral vice and literally a disease, I don’t think we should be convinced by that. All of this means that Plutarch’s exercises are not “ready-to-use” for OCD or for any pathological obsession.


    It is not obvious to me either that the theory behind those exercises is appropriate for other obsessions, even at the scale of the proverbial folly of humanity. This essay does not provide a nuanced discussion of the phenomenon of perceived salience and inquisitiveness. It is not so much a flaw of this essay as an initial misunderstanding on my part: something had been lost in translation. Indeed, what I had known as “On Curiosity” can also be translated as “On Being a Busybody”. What Plutarch talks about is a type of gossipy curiosity that moves people to stick their noses in other people’s businesses. The topic is even narrower than that, since he declares that this gossipy nature always has to do with wanting to learn about other people’s problems. He writes: "Such a malady of the mind, to take the first instance, is curiosity, which is a desire to learn the troubles of others"5 As the rest of the essay makes clear, “schadenfreude” is what he has in mind. This essay could have been called “On Schadenfreude”. Moreover, I do believe that even if we stick to the topic of schadenfreude, there are reasons to think he does not describe the actual psychology behind this phenomenon. He derives the desire to learn about other people’s failures from a kind of malevolence, "from a savage and bestial affliction, a vicious nature"6. Yet, this is to take things backwards. In reality, schadenfreude derives from a context where we are encouraged to compare ourselves to one another to see how well we are doing in life. Thus, “malignancy” is not a primary passion. It’s a secondary passion that can only exist on the back of heuristics we use to see how well we are doing compared to others. For this reason, I feel like this essay does not capture why gossip is attractive in the first place. Which is why the therapeutic argumentation that Plutarch lays out here does not work for me, and had to be replaced in my mind by my own version of “thinking about unhealthy curiosity”.


    That being said, it is possible that the entire point is to make gossipy curiosity look unattractive, without any concession. To say that Plutarch missed the actual psychology of the phenomenon might miss the fact that this moral exhortation is not necessarily interested in reconstructing such a psychology, and might be entirely comfortable with slander as a rhetorical device. Indeed, when I think about why I found those anti-curiosity exercises helpful, I realize that it is because they provided enthusiastic encouragements to turn away from obsessions, and while I do not find slander particularly helpful, I recognize that the moral condemnation is meant to contribute to the vigorous style of the exhortation. A vigorous style that I did find helpful. With a lot of caveats. I fully recognize that this is not for everyone. In particular, I think of all the OCD sufferers who would not be helped at all by moral condemnation and invitations to exert self-control. But since I took this training regimen with a grain of salt, and since it wasn’t my sole spiritual diet (I could not approach these exercises without supplementing them with mindfulness, and other tips and tricks I picked up along the way to deal with OCD) I wasn’t bothered as much by the downsides.


    During this entire month, I adopted this attitude of deliberately, stubbornly, and counter-intuitively turning away from my obsessions. As part of my OCD, I am a compulsive re-checker (prone to re-checking a dozen or more times that the front door is indeed locked, that the electrical appliances are indeed turned off, etc). It is incredibly difficult for me to break the pattern of obsessing over it and of engaging in compulsive rituals that are meant to serve the obsession (checking in a highly specific way ; for instance counting to 10 while trying the handle of the door with my hand positioned in a very precise way, etc). For this month, I decided to treat a lot of this like bad curiosity. Plutarch inspired me to try things progressively when he writes: "So first let us begin with the most trifling and unimportant matters. What difficulty is there about refraining from reading the inscriptions on tombs as we journey along the roads?"7 He invites us to train ourselves to let go by starting with challenges that have the lowest stakes imaginable. I took it as an invitation to challenge myself to completely let go of my OCD behaviour when the stakes are nonexistent or almost nonexistent. This is usually OCD behaviour that exists as a holdover from previous situations. For instance, I learned to check my mailbox in a specific way, because it was broken, but the OCD ritual remained even after the mailbox was replaced by a new one. These low-stake/no stake rituals proved to be a good training ground to cultivate a new attitude. I was then able to cultivate this attitude in contexts where it was scarier for me to do so.


    My incessant checking behaviour is mostly visual ; checking things with my eyes. I was therefore really inspired by the following passage (minus the reference to servants): "the faculty of vision should not be spinning about outside of us,​ like an ill‑trained servant girl, but when it is sent on an errand by the soul it should quickly reach its destination and deliver its message, then return again in good order within the governance of the reason and heed its command."8 I can relate to the idea of having my vision spin around as I double-check everything. Instead, I endeavored to simply look away, turn away from what seemed really relevant in the moment. A happy by-product of this experiment is that I came up with a system where I list all of my OCD triggers, and then assign to each OCD trigger the number of times I think it is reasonable to (re)check it. I decide in advance if it is worth checking once, twice, more, or not at all. The letting go was thus in service of a reasonable plan. At the best of times, it felt less like mustering self-control (which doesn’t really get you out of the stiffness of OCD) and more about escaping a situation as fast as I could. Here too Plutarch provided a bit of indirect inspiration: “neither is this a difficult nor arduous task: […] when a crowd is running to see something or other, to remain seated, or, if you are without self-control, to get up and go away. For you will reap no advantage from mixing yourself with busybodies, whereas you will obtain great benefit from forcibly turning aside your curiosity and curtailing it and training it to obey reason.”9


    “Forcibly”, “obedience”, “reason” ; there is a running theme here. We are called to exert self-control, will power. Such exhortations are very hit-or-miss depending whether you need just an extra-push (hit!) or another kind of help (miss!). Quite often, people think all we need is just an extra-push, when in fact we are at the end of our rope. For this reason, those encouragements are not, as they are in their current state, appropriate for OCD sufferers. I don’t think they constitute exclusively a call to exert self-control, since they are embedded in a therapeutic argumentation about gossipy curiosity, which is meant to be persuasive. But as I mentioned, those arguments about gossipy curiosity fail to be relevant. All of that said, the general idea behind those exercises was helpful to get me to a place of “exposure and response prevention”. What I found especially inspiring is that since those encouragements appear in the context of criticizing the allure of curiosity, it prepared me for the fact that exposure therapy required turning away from things that I found very salient in the moment. As Juliette Vazard points out, there is a relevance signal that goes haywire in OCD. I feel like Plutarch’s anti-curiosity exercises prepared me for the fact that I would have to turn away while in the middle of receiving this intense curiosity signal. As such, it is not a philosophical exercise that is very respectful of how OCD shapes the way I perceive the world, with anxious curiosity. This makes it an exercise that I don’t want to be using all the time. But I can see how it could be useful from time to time.



Pierrick Simon

31/01/2024

my email: lemiroirtranquille@outlook.fr

(do not hesitate to reach out)

my Bluesky: @pierricksimon.bsky.social


NOTES:

1https://penelope.uchicago.edu/Thayer/E/Roman/Texts/Plutarch/Moralia/De_curiositate*.html On Being a Busybody, by Plutarch as published in Vol. VI of the Loeb Classical Library edition, 1939. English translation by W. C. Helmbold.

3VAZARD, Juliette, (Un)reasonable doubt as affective experience: obsessive–compulsive disorder, epistemic anxiety and the feeling of uncertainty

4Paragraph 12

5Paragraph 1

6Paragraph 6

7Paragraph 11

8Paragraph 12

9Paragraph 13

Wednesday, January 3, 2024

The Trustful Approach: Some Considerations on the Theory Behind the Practice (Mindfulness, Phenomenology, Disagreements)

The following article was originally published as “The Trustful Approach: introducing an original philosophical exercise to live social discord mindfully” as it was meant to serve as a first introduction to this philosophical exercise. However, since it is a long article, which goes a lot into details regarding the theory behind the practice, and since my thinking has evolved regarding some aspects, I have since then published another post, which is a shorter and way better introduction to the exercise. I encourage you to read it. In the end, the new title of the present article reflects better what is in it.    

    The trustful approach is a philosophical exercise that I have developed in order to deal with heated disagreements and chronic outrage. It is especially tailored to political disagreements, though it can be useful in other cases. The aim of the practice is to make you a more focused, lucid, and serene interlocutor, without losing your grip on righteous indignation, should it be appropriate. It is called the “trustful approach” because it is meant to lead you to trust more that the person you disagree with do indeed mean what they say, while at the same time empowering you to express your own perspective. It is meant to have a clarifying effect on discourse and to promote resilience in the face of frequent political strife. Ultimately, the goal is to reduce toxic political polarization.

    I shall, first, explain the rationale of the practice, then talk through an example of a situation where the practice could be useful, and, finally, leave you with a set of instructions that are meant to facilitate practising the exercise.

    The Rationale

    How do you practice the trustful approach? It is designed to be a mindfulness-based method. Mindfulness meditation is a very specific attentional exercise. As Jan Puc puts it, “mindfulness consists in stopping the spreading of the affective force of a stimulus through the mind” and “Mindfulness meditation seeks to achieve this effect intentionally by instructing the meditator to focus her attention exclusively on the emergence and disappearance of objects in the focus of attention.”1. Therefore, the way you learn to practice the trustful approach is the following: 1) you learn to practice mindfulness meditation, 2) you put the theory of the trustful approach to the test during your mindfulness practice. The theory will provide ways to challenge the emotions specific to social discord. Now, is it useful to keep on reading this article if you do not know how to practice mindfulness meditation? Yes, I think so. Because I will say a few things about mindfulness that are as good a place as any to start being initiated into it.

    When it comes to mindfulness meditation, the little story that we like to tell is that striving hard to get what you think will make you happy often is the very thing that prevents you from experiencing the happiness that you aim for. The desire disturbs and obstructs the very happiness that it promises in exchange for its fulfilment. There is something suspicious about how fleeting contentment is following hard-won fulfilment of desire: it suggests a certain habit of desire that is not only not conducive to happiness, but actually the source of unhappiness. It is restlessness. It is “trying too hard”. It suggests, not just a certain impotence in appreciating what you have, but an active repudiation of the very thing you say you want. This “little story”, or to use a term coined by Martha Nussbaum, this “therapeutic argument”2 is what makes sense of the different heuristics used during mindfulness meditation. The difference between what counts as “being present” and “not being present”, what counts as “being judgmental” and “not being judgmental”, can all be traced back to the therapeutic argumentation. All the distinctions that might be puzzling to the uninitiated are explained by it. The trustful approach will borrow the rationale of mindfulness meditation for its own purposes and will have its own set of heuristics.

    Like much of mindfulness meditation, the trustful approach will focus on how desire manifests as a need for immediate cognitive closure: the attempt to think things through. On top of dealing with our more visible choices, the technique thus deals with all the mostly invisible thinking and ruminating that is being done in the service of trying to attain a certain state of affairs that should fully satisfy us. In reality, quite often, getting what we thought we needed prompts us only to start the cycle of striving all over again, either finding another pretext for discontentment or doubling down on the current one. The sheer speed of the cycle is, let’s face it, downright comical, when it is not tragic.

    But what of it in the case of social discord? We can feel indignation while witnessing what some people say or do, and that feeling of irritated shock comes together with exactly such a desire for immediate cognitive closure. We want to know what to make of the offence, what to think of the offence. But that cognitive desire has to be treated like all others desires: it is not necessarily wise to take it at face value. Desire can fail to deliver on its promise. Desire sometimes prevents the very contentment that it promises. A lot of emotional shock happens on the back of previous attempts to assuage our curiosity and settle the matter in question. Restlessness. Trying too hard. Our habits of mind not only fail to bring us closure, but they lead us to desire closure more and more, faster and faster, farther and farther from reality, thus planting the seeds of all the future emotional shocks to come. This is what the trustful approach teaches us to see.

    To do this, it relies on a heuristic. We are going to draw a distinction between surprise and shock. For the purpose of the exercise, we will define surprise as an emotional reaction to the unexpected and we will define shock as bewilderment (not knowing how to make sense of something)3. Having done that, we can now be attentive to several scenarios. 1) We are sometimes surprised but not shocked, as the unexpected event does not challenge our sense-making capacity. 2) We are sometimes surprised and shocked, as the unexpected event does challenge our sense-making capacity. 3) We are sometimes shocked, but not surprised, as our sense-making capacity is challenged, but we do not encounter something unexpected. This last scenario is the one that is the most interesting to us in the light of the suspicion of restlessness. It is an experience of a shock that feels like surprise, as it casts a shadow of strangeness on the object of attention, similar to the strangeness of the unexpected. Yet, in the midst of this experience, we can remember that we are not actually dealing with something unexpected, and we can gain a greater lucidity regarding what is actually going on. Indeed, as we are feeling the disbelief of indignation – “I cannot believe that they would do that” – it is good to check: can we really not believe, based on all we know so far? Or are we perhaps in a hurry to not believe, in a hurry to reach for new and better explanations? If so, we might want to check that this disbelief is not displacing pretty good explanations of the offensive behaviour that we already possess. Are we asking for more than what we already have, thus casting aside what we already have; i.e a satisfactory explanation of the offensive event? If we feel shock, this feeling that closely resembles surprise, in a situation where we are not actually facing something unexpected, it is time for us to pause and be mindful of our desire for cognitive closure. Do note that in the case of ongoing political disagreements, a lot of shocks might not be actual subversion of expectations, since we learn through experience what our political opponents are like. So when we are feeling the disbelief of indignation then, it is interesting to wonder what we might be giving up on through this disbelief, and what aspiration this “giving up” is allegedly in the service of.

    To introduce some nuance into this schematic exposé, let’s remark that it is not an all or nothing kind of situation. It is not a matter of either looking for closure or giving up on closure altogether. It is more about the details of how striving manifests itself. Perhaps we start craving more and more subtle and original explanations, at the expense of the explanations we already have. Indulging in this craving too much might make it worse in the long run. And what are the tacit assumptions behind that desire for subtlety and originality anyway? We need to pay attention to the wisdom of our desire and to the health of our curiosity. And for this, the devil is in the details. Details that an introduction to the philosophical exercise cannot fully capture. It is the meditation exercise itself that is meant to lead to discoveries.

    However, in choosing “trustful approach” as a name, I sought to give a bit of a taste of what I think the flavour of those details will be. There is a particular type of distrust in the other and in oneself that is a sign of restlessness. Time and again, we resist the idea that our political adversaries believe what they say they believe when they explain what they do. Thus, we are looking for the real reason for the offence, the explanation behind the explanation. In this way, it seems to us that the world is filled with people piloted by ulterior motives, either the allure of laziness, haste, and greed, or more complex allegiances to dogmas, factions, fellow conspirators, etc. The correlate of that is that we are unable to appreciate that this polemical explanation we endorse would enjoy a fuller expression of itself if it were properly articulated as our own particular point of view, and not as the secret point of view of others that we claim to uncover in extremis through detective work. Positing ulterior motives is often what happens when we lack confidence in our ability to criticize motives that are plain to see, and that our political adversaries are more than happy to tell us about.


    An Example

    Let’s discuss the case that Katie Stockdale writes about in Moral Shock, which is the anecdote of how she was shocked by sexist remarks in her classroom:

“Consider my experience of moral shock in a classroom setting. In the middle of teaching, a student raised his hand. I called on him. He asked the question: ‘When do you plan to have children?’ I was shocked. I could feel my eyes widen and face heat up imagining its redness visible to my students; and I eventually replied, without the ability to look directly at him, ‘that’s an inappropriate question, so I am moving on’. After class, I was disappointed in myself for my non-ideal response. If I were to have considered in advance of the class what I ought to do if a student asked such a question, I would have chosen to act differently. I might have intended to respond by looking at the student, directly in the eyes, and explaining why the question is inappropriate. But in the moment, I was incapacitated by moral shock.

One thing that interests me about moral shock is that it challenges us to question to what extent our expectations about how people will behave have a grip on us. In this case, I experienced moral shock despite my expectations about how I will be treated by male students in the classroom. I expect that, when I am teaching, I will receive unwanted, sexually suggestive, or challenging remarks from some of my male students at some point throughout the semester; it happens all the time. And I naturally believe, in a Humean way, that the future will resemble the past. This particular student had also made a series of inappropriate comments throughout the semester, so I anticipated more to come. But my expectations about students’ behavior in the classroom, and this student’s behavior in particular, did not prevent my shock at the immoral act. Why might we find ourselves shocked by immoral behavior we fully expected from others?”4

    Katie Stockdale then goes on to defend the idea that “the extent to which a person will be shocked by an intensely bewildering event depends not on the extent to which it violated their expectations, but rather how prepared they were, emotionally, to be in the midst of it.”5. Later, in discussing a different public speaking-related challenge, she proposes the idea that the possibility of “emotional preparation” confirms her thesis, indeed: “To feel ready for surviving a difficult Q & A, the speaker might practice how he will manage his emotions in response to a tough question when it arises – by breathing through the anxiety, displaying confident body language to counter-act self-doubt, etc. He might even practice (e.g., in front of a mirror, to his partner) these strategies, inhabiting his future agency as much as he can so that the experience, when it occurs, is much less physically and emotionally difficult to endure. However prepared a speaker might be to give a talk in terms of practicing the talk itself, and anticipating potential questions and objections, if the speaker is not emotionally prepared for surviving a difficult Q & A, he might find himself caught off guard and unable to respond to difficult questions – even those that he expected to be articulated”6

    When I juxtapose these two anecdotes, it gives the impression that the teacher who receives misogynistic remarks can prepare herself emotionally in order to handle the situation well. If shock happens when we are not emotionally prepared to be in the challenging situation, and if it is possible to train oneself to be more emotionally prepared, then it means that we can prepare ourselves for these challenging situations. This is a very contentious proposition. Is that resilience possible? Even if it is possible, is it even desirable? It could be suspected, for instance, that this proposition focuses on the behaviour of the victim and fails to face the injustice, to articulate the way the offender is the one who should have behaved differently. Indignation serves the purpose of making you attentive to that. Are we going to ignore it? I am moving away from how Katie Stockdale might choose to answer these concerns with her theoretical framework, and I am instead acknowledging that this problem hits hardest the theoretical framework that underlies the trustful approach. What is this philosophical exercise telling us about this situation and how it can be improved? I believe that, in the end, we can articulate how there’s room for improvement, without cancelling the benefits of indignation.

    Let’s examine the situation properly. What kind of person asks, in the middle of class, about when the teacher is planning to have children? It is the kind of person who is shocked about all the wrong things. Who knows what it is exactly that set them off, but at the end of the day, we know that this is the kind of person who would be shocked if they thought a woman didn’t plan on having children, or if a woman didn’t think she owed him a report on her situation, or if a woman showed excellence in her career, in a way that seems remote from “motherly duties”, etc… He is shocked! And so the teacher is shocked in return – shocked by what he finds shocking – and in turn, the student might be shocked by her reaction, he might exclaim: “I was just asking a simple question?!”. And so on and so forth. Shock and counter-shock is an instrument of mutual disclosure of values7. Such polarization is not necessarily bad. In the present case, polarization is absolutely instrumental in allowing feminism to win by having misogynists reveal themselves and people feel like they have to pick a side on whether misogyny is okay or not. Yet, the present situation is not necessarily ideal. People can still pay attention in better ways, conversations can still be unproductive if we’re not careful.

    If the student were trained in the trustful approach, he might start noticing things that he had not noticed before about how he feels in the situation. For instance, he might notice that he is shocked by the fact that the teacher is being a teacher, in the way that she is, even though it is a fact that shouldn’t be surprising to him since he is aware of that situation already. Noticing that gap might make him aware that, in his indignation, he is pushing away the most straightforward explanation for this state of affairs: the teacher believes that this is the best use of her time, based on the values that she holds. This straightforward explanation is in stark contrast with other inflammatory explanations that disclose the act of being a teacher as a desire to be the center of attention, to lord one’s ‘subversive’ status (that’s how it appears to the misogynist) over the students, etc, in short: as a challenge to be addressed. Thus, the class setting might stop being disclosed to the attention of this student as the best setting to challenge one another’s views about how to lead one’s personal life. Thus, we go from a sexist student who raises their hand, to a sexist student who doesn’t raise their hand. The first benefit is that it does not create the counter-shock of the teacher, which might motivate further entrenchment (how can one question one’s self when one feels that people can’t take a “simple innocent question” or “can’t take a joke”?). Far from leaving the sexism embedded in the attentional pattern of the student unnoticed and unchecked, it directly modifies those attentional patterns: if the female teacher is not immediately ‘challenging’ on sight, she can be seen as a teacher, and not as a woman who is making a ‘big deal’ out of being a teacher. There is absolutely no guarantee that a sexist student might be open to undergoing this kind of training, but it is good to not rule it out a priori.

    What of the shocked teacher? Is improvement possible there? She might express a wish for empowerment, like Stockdale does, as we have seen: After class, I was disappointed in myself for my non-ideal response. If I were to have considered in advance of the class what I ought to do if a student asked such a question, I would have chosen to act differently. I might have intended to respond by looking at the student, directly in the eyes, and explaining why the question is inappropriate. But in the moment, I was incapacitated by moral shock.”8 I think that this wish can make sense and that we can have good hope of it being fulfilled, though I do not mean to suggest that it is necessarily appropriate in all scenarios. It entirely depends on the circumstances. I think that, in some situations, the trustful approach might help with that. We know the behaviour of the student was shocking, but hardly unexpected. In that gap, maybe we will start noticing some interesting things.

    Maybe the teacher felt at a loss for words because she felt that there was a very high bar to clear: to meet the student’s dismissive gaze and, in spite of his scoffing, to meet his entrenched world-view with an articulate and convincing explanation while avoiding to ridicule herself in front of a potentially tough crowd. In other words: a halo of invulnerability might have been perceived around the student and the crowd. And this felt-sense of a high bar to clear, this embodied sense of missing the means, could potentially have been prepared by certain habits of mind that the trustful approach can address. Certain habits having to do with how one thinks about this student or people like them. Indeed, as we ruminate about him, (“Seriously?! What was this guy thinking?!” -How can you still be sexist in [insert the current year]?!” - “How can you get through to people so lost?!” - “Did he not realize? Or, on the contrary, realized all too well?”) we might repudiate straightforward explanations and adopt skewed explanations instead. We might repudiate the idea that this person is an indignant sexist who is trying to express his values. Indeed, I suggested earlier that the student is shocked, and that this explains his behaviour. I did not feel like a lot of detective work was needed to uncover the fact that he was shocked, instead, I felt that this was not a hidden truth but the very meaning of his utterance (the question he asked). Simply put, he is communicating sincerely enough. But we have a habit sometimes of refusing to see this, and to try to adopt skewed explanations instead: he was not a sincere communicator because he was trying to be the center of attention, or he was trying to get a reaction, to hurt, to joke, to prank, etc. Those explanations are skewed not because they describe things that cannot possibly be there at all, but because they split motives like one would split hairs, and side-step the central motivation that is plain to see: you want to grab attention when you have something to say, you want people to be impacted by your words when you have something to say, you want to convey what looks “funny” to you when you joke etc. So this person felt that they had something worthwhile to say! To engage in the trustful approach is to come out of the haze of looking for ulterior motives when a straightforward explanation would do: the student was shocked, and so they reacted because they felt they had something to say.

    Splitting motives leads to unnecessary and unhelpful theories. For instance, one might take the worry that the student was trying to be the center of attention, and start hypothesizing that he is, in fact, not a convinced misogynist himself, but just happens to take on this mantle to make a scene. Once this hypothesis sets in, the student is now perceived with the aforementioned halo of invulnerability: in these conditions, what could we possibly say that wouldn’t already be fully anticipated by this cruel set-up? It becomes difficult to meet his gaze, to muster the will to say something. What’s the point? He is being sexist, but he can’t be reasoned with, and we are making a fool of ourselves. The above wrong-headed hypothesis might seem like an “extreme” example, as it puts forward a pretty useless guess, making the offender sexist in a very roundabout way. But it is actually an example of a pretty widespread style of thinking about this type of event, making me worry that many would not find it an extreme example. This sort of hypothesis starts from a place of disbelief at the apparent motivation of the offender, and then crosses into a search for hidden motivations. It creates useless guesses that are useful only to scare oneself: if the person is performatively sexist, they are still sexist, except... What can you do about it? Outperform them surely. The recurring theme seems to be that a grievance we have against the offender is fully elevated to the status of insight into their psyche (“they hurt us, they must be a sadist”, “cruelty is the point”), which unsurprisingly fixes the estrangement we feel firmly in place. We thus conflate our own perspective on the situation, however justified it may be, with their psychology. As a result, the psyche of the offender seems as deep, mysterious, and invulnerable, as we feel impotent, and vice-versa.

    Many different worries can lead to many different unhelpful hypotheses, not all having to do with literally thinking the person is not a convinced misogynist, but all having pretty similar consequences: they make the offender appear unreachable, untouchable, and so they make us lose our means. I propose the idea that if the teacher is indeed in the grip of those unhelpful ideas, various exercises, such as mindfulness meditation, can revise the underlying insecurities and improve the situation. (It is also perfectly possible that there are no such corrigible insecurities to be found in any given case, but my point is only that it makes sense to check, using the trustful approach, because sometimes they are interesting things to notice.) I believe that the trustful approach is not doomed to unfairly center our attention on the behaviour of the victim, at the expense of condemning the perpetrator, given that, not only are we able to articulate the fault of the perpetrator with the vocabulary of this exercise, but the therapy offered to the victim is directly dependent on a discussion of the fault of the perpetrator, as we have seen. We seek to face the injustice as straightforwardly as possible, weeding out tempting excuses for the behaviour of the perpetrator at the same time as we weed out skewed psychological explanations. By the same token, we give ourselves the tools to notice when we are in the wrong, or when no one is, or when we all are.

    The Instructions.

I am now leaving you with instructions to practice the exercise.

If you have not practised mindfulness meditation before, you have to learn how to do it. Resources for this abound on the internet9.

If you do know how to practice mindfulness, then take the following text as a checklist that allows you to notice all that is relevant to notice when you focus your attention on indignation. At first, memorize and call to mind the phrases of this checklist that you find most helpful. Soon enough, you will have internalized those instructions and you will probably have no need to recall those phrases.

Here is the checklist:

- In the manner characteristic of mindfulness meditation, notice and contemplate your feeling of indignation whenever it arises. Try to recall: are you shocked & surprised, or are you shocked, but not surprised? If you are genuinely surprised, it makes sense to wonder how best you can satisfy your curiosity regarding the shocking event. But if you are not surprised, and yet feeling shocked, it makes sense instead to examine where your renewed curiosity is taking you. Are you drifting away from what you already know? Are you pushing away simpler and more reasonable explanations of the event? Are you desiring newer and subtler explanations faster and faster?

- Notice how strange and bewildering the offensive behaviour and the offender seem. How quick the repudiation of previously established knowledge is. How alluring the desire for cognitive closure is ; its promise of satisfaction. How urgent and pointed your sense of duty feels, as someone who feels they have to respond to this situation. And most of all, notice the solidarity between those four aspects of shock, how one contains all the others. How estrangement from the mind of the offender is the correlate of your renewed desire to make sense of things.

- Be attentive to those things most of all when you are trying to read the minds of others, trying to understand what they must be thinking. Does the mind of the offender feel like an impenetrable black box, an unsettling mystery? Does it feel like a halo of invulnerability protects the offender from being reached, one that simultaneously calls for new tactics of engagement and thwarts them at every turn? In those conditions, notice if you are splitting their motivation into caricatural motives, such as: attention seeking, sadism, etc.

- How does indignation feel as it spreads through the mind?

***

Pierrick Simon

03/01/2024

my email: lemiroirtranquille@outlook.fr

(do not hesitate to reach out ; especially if you want to try out the trustful approach)


1 Puc, J. (2019). In Defence of Bare Attention: A Phenomenological Interpretation of Mindfulness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 (5-6). p.182

2 Nussbaum, Martha. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. REV-Revised. Princeton University Press, 1994. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt2tt8tt.

3 For those conceptual considerations, I am indebted to Katie Stockdale. But these concepts are modified for my own purposes. See: Stockdale, Katie (2022). Moral Shock. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 8 (3):496-511. And also see my response to it: Simon, Pierrick (2023). Shocking Others: a Phenomenology of Emotional Shock and Political Polarization. Kultura i Wartości ISSN 2299-7806 Nr 36.

4 Stockdale, Katie (2022). Moral Shock. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 8 (3):496-497.

5 Moral Shock. p.498.

6 Moral Shock. p.505.

7 Osler, Lucy (2023). WTF?! Covid-19, Indignation, and the Internet. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 22 (5):1-20.

8 Moral Shock. p.496.

9 If you do not know where to begin, a trustworthy source is « Waking Up » created by Sam Harris. Looking around on the internet should make you discover Waking-Up adjacent content for free where Sam Harris teaches you how to meditate. Otherwise there is the app « Waking Up », with a free trial, a subscription, OR, for those of us who cannot afford the subscription, you can request a « scholarship »: no strings attached, no questions asked, they grant you a free subscription if you cannot afford it otherwise, here: https://app.wakingup.com/scholarship

The Trustful Approach: an Introduction

The trustful approach is a philosophical exercise that teaches you peace of mind and confidence in the face of political disagreement and so...